-->

Loss Aversion Most Complete From Sopintar

Loss Aversion Most Complete From Sopintar - Hello friend sopintar.blogspot.com SCIENCE & NEWS, In the article that you read this time with the title Loss Aversion Most Complete From Sopintar , we have prepared this article well for you to read and retrieve information in it. hopefully fill in the post Artikel Economists, Artikel Interesting Papers, Artikel Thesis topics, what we write can you understand. OK, happy reading.


link : Loss Aversion Most Complete From Sopintar
A frequent email correspondent asked "I�d love to hear your take on �loss aversion.� I just finished listening to Kahneman�s book." My response seems worth sharing with blog readers.

Expected Utility



Let�s review expected utility first. The utility you get from consumption or wealth is a concave function of consumption or wealth. An extra dollar makes you more happy than it makes Bill Gates. So, compare either getting C for sure, or a 50/50 bet of getting C+Delta or C-Delta, i.e. having C or betting 50/50 on a coin flip. The expected utility of C for sure is just U(C). The expected utility of the bet is

EU = prob(loss) * U(consumption if loss) + prob(gain) * U(consumption if gain)

EU = 1/2 * U(C - Delta) + 1/2 * U(C + Delta).

As the graph shows, this is less than the expected utility of C for sure. So, people should decline fair value bets. They are �risk averse�.

Comments. Behavioral fans (New York times has done this often in its economics coverage) criticize �classical economics� by saying it ignores the fact that people fear losses more than they value gains. That�s absolutely false. Look at the utility function. People fear losses more than they value gains. That�s the whole point of expected utility. (You�ll see the confusion in a second).

A common mistake: EU( C) is not the same as U [ E(C )]. You do not find the utility of expected consumption, you find the expected utility of consumption. In my graph, C is equal to the expected value of C-Delta and C+Delta, and the whole point is that the utility of C is bigger than the expected utility of (C-Delta) or (C+Delta). You can take E inside a linear function, but you cannot take E inside a nonlinear function.

Loss aversion

OK, on to loss aversion. In the usual sort of experiments Kahneman found that people seem reluctant to lose money. They have a �reference point� and work  hard to avoid bets that might put them below that reference point. He models that as expected utility with a kink in it, as in the second drawing.

I was careful to draw the reference point as different than C. People do not necessarily place the reference point at the expected value of the bet. In fact, usually they don�t. If betting on stocks, the expected value of the bet is to gain 7% per year. The �don�t lose money� point would be do not go below 0, not do not go below the mean. Here people are especially afraid only of the very left part of the distribution.

Now, really, how are these models different? Expected utility can be any function, and nobody said it doesn�t have a kink in it. The key distinguishing feature of loss aversion � and its Achilles heel � is that the reference point shifts around. If you make some money, and play again, then your kink shifts up to the new amount of money you made. Expected utility is supposed to stay the same function of consumption or wealth. People might change behavior � most likely the utility curve is flatter at high levels of consumption, so rich people are less risk averse. But the curve itself does not shift. The key assumption that distinguishes loss aversion from expected utility is that the kink point shifts around as you gain and lose money.

That�s also the Achilles heel.  The first problem is how do you handle sequential bets. If I go to the casino, and know I will play twice, how do I think about my strategy? With expected utility this is easy, because the expected utility works backwards. Suppose you win the first bet, then figure out what you do in the second bet. For each of win or loss in the first bet, then, you have an expected utility from taking the second bet. The expected utility of the first bet is then the expected vaule of the expected utilities you would have if you won or lost.



Equations might be better than words. Let Chh, Chl, Clh, and Cll be consumption if you win twice, win and then lose, lose and then win, lose and then lose, and U(Chh), U(Chl), etc be their utilities. So, suppose you won the first bet. You evaluate the second bet by

EUh == EU given you won first bet = Ph*U(Chh) + Pl*U(Chl).

Similarly, if you lost the first bet, then

EUl = Eu given you lost the first bet = Ph*U(Clh) + Pl*U(Lll).

So now, the expected utility of the first bet is just a one-stage bet, with these expected utilities as payoffs.

EU = Ph *Euh + Pl*EUl

I won�t go through more equations, but the same thing holds for decisions. You can work optimal decisions backwards.

Now, this all gets to be a big problem with loss aversion. The key question: Do loss averse people in stage 1 think about the fact that if they win or lose in stage 1 that will change their reference point for stage 2? Again, the reference point must shift, or we just have expected utility. If people ignore that their actions today shift the reference point tomorrow, then they�re unbelievably dumb. If people don�t, then we have a mess on our hands. Since your preferences today disagree with your preferences tomorrow, you might act strategically, deliberately winning or losing today to shift the reference point for tomorrow and influence how you will behave tomorrow. There have been brave papers trying to work this out (Barberis, Huang and Santos) but the result has been, in my view, so complex that it hasn�t come in to common use.

But really to be useful in economics or finance, we have to have a model that does not apply just to wake up, make a bet, eat, die, but that describes how people make decisions over a lifetime, and with knowledge that they will bet many times.

Some more problems with loss aversion: We certainly see lots of individual behavior that suggests reference points. People get really reluctant to sell houses for less than they bought them for, for example. The problem here is that expected utility refers to your overall wealth. You don�t mind losing on your house, say, if you gained in your stocks, or if the new house you want to buy also went down in price, as your overall wealth or consumption does not change. Now, to apply loss aversion, it seems we need to define loss aversion as a function of each individual purchase, not overall consumption. You need �mental accounting� as well, of which items go into which pot, and a rule not to lose on individual pots, as well as loss aversion.

A deeper skepticism about "irrationality" 

I have a deeper skepticism about the rush to label people irrational (and us researchers oh so much smarter). What�s so irrational about following a rule or heuristic that says, avoid losing money on your trades? Another widely adduced �irrationality� is that people tend to trade too much. Given that prices often do bounce back, the heuristic �don�t lose money on your trades� might be a useful guide. Most buying and selling often involves a negotiation. Don�t sell at a loss helps you to avoid sharp negotiators. It�s also a good precommitment device. Real estate agents keep telling us �well, they won�t take that offer because they�d sell at a loss� even when they bought at the peak in 2007.

Likewise, �when people in lab coats come and tell you what the probabilities of things are and offer you bets on them, don�t believe them because they�re trying to trick you� is a pretty good heuristic in life. You are going to run in to a lot more people playing 3 card monte or offering Bernie Madoff investments, and people in lab coats trying to prove you�re a moron,  than you are going to run in to honest researchers explaining how the game really works.

Apparently irrational rules are in fact often good rules for actual life. �Don�t pay attention to sunk costs� say economists, but if you run away from every half finished project because it�s a sunk cost, you don�t get anything done in life. Paying attention to sunk costs is a good way to make sure you actually finish writing, revising, and publishing papers! We live in a deeply information overload environment, and we have limited processing capacity. A lot of apparently irrational behavior seems to me decent rules of thumb for daily life, that appear irrational when extrapolated out of context to cleverly constructed environments that people have never seen before and have little experience with.

Mental accounting is similar. The accounting department of the University of Chicago Booth school, home of efficient markets, subdivides the school�s money into thousands of separate budget items with a rule that  you can�t lose money on any individual one. If you buy and extra bottle of wine on the seminar budget, you can�t offset that even if at the end of the year there is money left over in the Pizzas for MBAs budget. Such budgeting is a practically universal method of controlling costs in all large organizations. It sure feels stupid, but is it really given the information problems?

Moreover, if people do behave this way, there is a way to make a huge amount of money off of them. Asset prices are smooth functions of gains or losses. Suppose your reference point is, you don�t want to lose more than $1000 on stocks. By buying stocks and options, I can create a portfolio that will never lose more than $1000. The price of the downside insurance is a smooth function of that loss point, so it will be cheaper for me to buy that downside insurance than it will be for me to sell it to you. Or you can buy it for yourself. There is a lot of behavioral study of people�s portfolios and the nutty investments they make, but we do not see pervasive buying of such downside insurance options, nor do we see the large prices such options would have if people were all loss averse.

In sum, I prefer when seeing unusual behavior to ask a bit harder "just what question is this the right answer to?" before rushing to say people are dumb and ask the government to nudge them my way.

Habits and others



Since I worked on it, I have to mention one halfway alternative � habits. See the  graph. Suppose people have a lower level of consumption that they really don�t want to go below. The obvious lower bound is starvation, but we all develop habits of consumption that would be super-painful to change.  A hedge fund manager�s wife once said at a cocktail party �I�d sooner die than fly commercial again,� and that can be represented by the habit level as well.

Now, as it is, that�s just another expected utility function. But here too, we make the habit point move around depending on experience. The hedge fund manager�s wife was once middle class like us and thought the peanuts on Southwest were a grand treat. As you consume more, or as you observe your neighbors and friends consume more, the minimum acceptable level of consumption rises. It can also model debts and fixed costs -- don't lose so much money that you have to sell the house and move into an apartment.

One reason this is different than loss aversion is that it turns out to be much more tractable for the dynamic question � how do you treat multiple bets. Not having a kink wandering around helps a lot. The strategic element is there. If the habit depends on your consumption, not your neighbor�s, then when you consume more you reset your habits. You might know this ahead of time, and we can work out easily how you behave. Habits make consumption an addictive good, so when thinking about eating more today, you recognize that it will influence how you feel tomorrow. When you drink another cappuccino today, you know it will make you want another one tomorrow, and are less likely to drink today as a result. We can work those things out easily.

That doesn�t address the mental accounting issues, the tendency to treat bets in isolation rather than as parts of a portfolio, and so forth. But it does capture the tendency to really avoid large losses, and how what a loss is shifts over time in response to gains and losses in wealth.

Two other popular approaches model a lot of challenging behavior as well. Recursive or Epstein-Zin utility is a non-expected utility model that captures lab experiments and is also analytically tractable, so it's becoming very common in macroeconomics and asset pricing. Lars Hansen is also been on a long research agenda of even more general utility functions that are  "ambiguity averse," capturing that people shrink away from uncertainty that they really don't know the probabilities of. Alas, once there is a clear and tractable mathematical model, people like this seem not welcome in the behavioral finance club, which says more about academic politics than about substantive matters.

I hope that helps!

PS to all:  Grumpy is back! I was traveling a lot making frequent blog posts difficult.

Update: An email correspondent writes
If a home was purchased at $500,000 with a mortgage of $450,000, and it is now sold for less than even $475,000, then after commissions and closing costs, the seller has less than $450,000 in hand and will be required to �bring cash to the closing� in order to fully pay off the bank.  Generally, families with homes selling for below mortgage value have trouble raising any cash at all.  All this is further complicated by the problem of where and how can the seller move to next if all his cash is put into getting out of the current mortgage?  No money for new down payment, or first month�s rent and deposit. The current owner is truly stuck at an above market offering price.
This is a good point. Fixed costs and transactions costs can give rise to the extra costs of a loss, and produce a kink. People who develop rules of thumb in that circumstance may not notice the lab experiment is cleverly designed not to have the actual costs of many real-world losses.




This is the article Loss Aversion Most Complete From Sopintar

So many articles Loss Aversion Most Complete From Sopintar this time, hopefully it can benefit you all. OK, see you in another article.

Also read


Loss Aversion Most Complete From Sopintar

You are now reading the article Loss Aversion Most Complete From Sopintar with the link address https://sopintar.blogspot.com/2018/09/loss-aversion-most-complete-from.html

Berlangganan update artikel terbaru via email:

Iklan Atas Artikel

Iklan2

Iklan Tengah Artikel 2

Iklan Bawah Artikel